Philosophie botanique de Charles Linné (1788)

Philosophie botanique de Charles Linné ... : dans laquelle sont expliqués les fondements de la botanique : avec les définitions de ses parties, les exemples des termes, des observations sur les plus rares ... (1788)


Read more...

Buddhism Books

Books on Buddhism, logics, and philosophy

A Short History of Buddhist Logic in Tibet (pdf)

The Conflict Between the Buddhist and the Naiyāyika Philosophers: a Brief Survey (pdf)

The Godliness of Buddhism (pdf)


Read more...

The Confessions of Augustine: An Electronic Edition

http://i292.photobucket.com/albums/mm7/catatando/gozzoli6.jpg

This document is an on-line reprint of Augustine: Confessions, a text and commentary by James J. O'Donnell (Oxford: 1992; ISBN 0-19-814378-8). The text and commentary were encoded in SGML by the Stoa Consortium in co-operation with the Perseus Project; the HTML files were generated from the archival SGML version.

Each book of the text has a link to introductory commentary on that book, and each section of the text has a link to detailed comments on the section. Links within the commentary connect not only to the section of text directly being annotated, but also to other parts of the text and commentary. Footnotes in the commentary appear at the end of each book; the footnote numbers are links from the commentary text to the footnote and from the footnote text back to the commentary. Where possible, links have been provided to the texts of classical works and Biblical passages cited in the commentary. Links at the end of each book of the text and commentary allow navigation to the next book or the previous one of text, commentary, or both together.


Read more...

Sample Chapters in Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy

Read more...

John H. Zammito - Médecin-philosoph: Persona for Radical Enlightenment

In 1772 Ernst Platner published Anthropologie für Ärzte und Weltweise. I want to consider how that combination of “physicians” and “philosophers” got into his title by recovering a peculiar mode of philosophical self-presentation that became crucial in Europe in the middle of the 18th century, the médecin-philosoph. I will connect the idea with the “paradigm shift” to “vital materialism” in French life science around mid-century in the works of Buffon, Maupertuis, La Mettrie and Diderot, stressing how the last two figures, in particular, took up the stance of the médecin-philosoph. I will then show how a parallel tradition took shape in Germany, culminating in Platner’s book.
John H. Zammito (Rice University): Médecin-philosoph: Persona for Radical Enlightenment


Read more...

Roberto Palaia - Ernst Platner avversario della Filosofia critica (1985)

Ernst Platner avversario della Filosofia critica

Read more...

Research Project on Romantic Anthropology

link

Today, the word "anthropology" means either the philosophical consideration of mankind and its special position in nature or the ethnological study of early cultures. These two definitions are only partly compatible with the way that this term was used during the Enlightenment and the Romantic period.

It is no coincidence that anthropology has its roots in the Renaissance - it is a discipline which is firmly grounded in the modern era, no longer drawing on metaphysics but instead looking to the here and now of human existence, combining philosophical ambitions with physiological and psychological questions. Thus, from its beginnings on, anthropology looked at issues which today would be considered medical, psychological, or philosophical as well as anthropological in the modern sense.

This interest in the "whole man" allowed anthropology to become a fundamental discipline in the late Enlightenment, a period which dedicated itself to the empirical study of man. Deductive reasoning, based on the universally applicable truths of reason (for example Christian Wolff's rationalistic philosophy which was so central to the early Enlightenment in Germany), was replaced by inductive thinking in which the relationship between "body" and "soul" was examined through self observation and the collection of case studies.

Thus, the last third of the 18th century saw the publication of numerous anthropological monographs – the first and most famous being Ernst Platner's Anthropologie für Ärzte und Weltweise (1772) – and periodicals – for example the Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde (1783-93, pub. Karl Phillip Moritz). Even the novelists of the period were interested in the study of the "whole man", and considered their literary work as a part of the anthropological project; Karl Phillip Moritz's Anton Reiser, Wieland's Agathon, Goethe's Werther and Schiller's Räuber can all be included here.

Read more...

Ernst Platner: Anthropologie für Ärzte und Weltweise (1772)

img145/4266/anthropologiefraerzteunpo5.jpg

Anthropologie für Aerzte und Weltweise. Leipzig 1772

Ernst Platner’s Anthropologie für Aerzte und Weltweise (1772) became the focus of a new intellectual fashion during the period of the late Enlightenment, where anthropology denotes a concept explaining the interaction of body and soul through physical influence. This theory was advocated by the so called ’philosophical doctors‘, who combined metaphysics with medicine. Platner, professor of both discip-lines in Leipzig, was the leading figure of the movement.

The imoprtance of Platner’s work within the intellectual history was recently rediscovered by several historians of both medicine and literature. Its innovative image of the human being can be found not only in the science of psychology, but also in the ’anthropological novel’, in autobiographical characterisations as well as in the ’natural theater‘ of Lessing’s time.

Only a few copies of Platner’s Anthropologie exist in library collections today. [source]

Read more...

Kant - Théorie et pratique par J.M. Muglioni

Cet ouvrage de Jean-Michel Muglioni sur Théorie et pratique de Kant, anciennement publié dans la collection Profil d'une oeuvre chez Hatier, est repris ici grâce au soutien de Laurence Hansen-Løve, ancienne directrice de la collection.
Voici un opuscule peu connu de Kant, qui a ma connaissance, n'est publié en français que chez Vrin sous le titre Sur l'expression courante: il se peut que ce soit juste en théorie, mais en pratique cela ne vaut rien et dans l'ancienne édition Profil, chez Hatier, que nous reprenons ici. La présentation et les commentaires mais également la traduction originale sont Jean-Michel Muglioni, professeur en première supérieure au lycée Louis-le-grand à Paris.
Ce texte est l'occasion pour Kant d'aborder des thèmes par ailleurs présents dans son oeuvre, qui concernent la morale et la politique, mais sous l'angle du rapport entre la théorie et la pratique.
En un mot, contrairement à «l'expression courante: c'est bon en théorie, mais non en pratique», la théorie oriente l'action et lui donne sens. Kant prend ici «la défense de la raison et de la pensée comme principes de l'action humaine.»

kant - théorie et pratique

Read more...

The Simpsons and Philosophy eBook

Read more...

Philosophical Investigations/Philosophische Untersuchungen


Philosophical Investigations
Blackwell Publishers
1998-02
ISBN: 0631205691
272 pages PDF 21 MB


The Philosophical Investigations of Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) present his own distillation of two decades of intense work on the philosophies of mind, language and meaning.Wittgenstein's importance to philosophy has, paradoxically, been overstated and understated at the same time.It is overstated when individuals attach themselves to particular arguments and use them to justify dubious claims - and, I might add, this is what happens more often than not. Half understood, some of these arguments seem to carry a weight that they do not have, and muddy things up more than they help.But understood in its entirety, W.'s philosophy is the most powerful and innovative (and I would say, correct) philosophy in recent times.Enjoy this great book! Brought to you by SMIRK

Read more...

The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy)


The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy)
Cambridge University Press
1999-07-01
ISBN: 0521446678
460 pages PDF 25,3 MB


The Western tradition of philosophy began in Greece with a cluster of thinkers often called the Presocratics, whose influence has been incalculable. All these thinkers are discussed in this volume both as individuals and collectively in chapters on rational theology, epistemology, psychology, rhetoric and relativism, justice, and poetics. Assuming no knowledge of Greek or prior knowledge of the subject, this volume provides new readers with the most convenient and accessible guide to early Greek philosophy available. Advanced students and specialists will find a conspectus of recent developments in the interpretation of early Greek thought.Enjoy this great book! Brought to you by SMIRK


Read more...

From Peirce to Skolem (Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics)


From Peirce to Skolem (Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics)
North Holland
2000-07-01
ISBN:044450334X
625 pages PDF 19 MB


This book is an account of the important influence on the development of mathematical logic of Charles S. Peirce and his student O.H. Mitchell, through the work of Ernst Schröder, Leopold Löwenheim, and Thoralf Skolem. As far as we know, this book is the first work delineating this line of influence on modern mathematical logic.Enjoy this great book! Brought to you by SMIRK.






Read more...

Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again


Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again
Andy Clark
MIT Press
1998-01-09
ISBN: 0262531569
291 pages PDF 1,4 MB


In Being There, Andy Clark weaves these several threads into a pleasing whole and goes on to address foundational questions concerning the new tools and techniques needed to make sense of the emerging sciences of the embodied mind. Clark brings together ideas and techniques from robotics, neuroscience, infant psychology, and artificial intelligence. He addresses a broad range of adaptive behaviors, from cockroach locomotion to the role of linguistic artifacts in higher-level thought. Enjoy this great book! Brought to you by SMIRK


Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again


Read more...

The Coherence of Kant's Transcendental Idealism


The Coherence of Kant's Transcendental Idealism
Publisher: Springer(2004-05-11)
ISBN-10: 1402025807
PDF 2.3 Mb 295 pages


This book presents a new interpretation of Kant’s theory of knowledge that emphasizes the coherence and plausibility of his doctrine of transcendental idealism. Many interpreters believe that Kant’s transcendental idealism is an incoherent theory. Some have attempted to respond to this charge. Yet, as the author demonstrates, the interpretations that seek to vindicate Kant’s theory continue to be committed to some claims that evoke the charge of incoherence. One type of claim which does so is connected to the contradictory notion of subjective necessity. The other type of claim is related to the supposition that knowledge of the reality of appearances entails knowledge of the reality of things in themselves. The interpretation presented in this book does not involve any of these claims. Part One of this book presents an analysis of Kant’s concept of a priori knowledge and of his response to skepticism about synthetic a priori knowledge that specifies the content of such knowledge without invoking the notion of subjective necessity. Part Two presents an account of the non-spatiotemporality of things in themselves that does not entail knowledge of the reality of things in themselves. Part Three presents a new interpretation of transcendental synthesis, the transcendental "I" and of the role of transcendental self-consciousness in synthetic a priori knowledge which emphasizes the originality of Kant’s account of self-knowledge and subjectivity. The arguments presented in this book relate Kant’s ideas to current debates in epistemology, metaphysics and the philosophy of mind in a way that underscores their invaluable relevance to present-day philosophical discourse.

Read more...

The Cambridge Companion to Descartes

Descartes occupies a position of pivotal importance as one of the founding fathers of modern philosophy; he is, perhaps the most widely studied of all philosophers. In this authoritative collection an international team of leading scholars in Cartesian studies present the full range of Descartes’ extraordinary philosophical achievement. His life and the development of his thought, as well as the intellectual background to and reception of his work, are treated at length. At the core of the volume are a group of chapters on his metaphysics: the celebrated ‘Cogito’ argument, the proofs of God’s existence, the ‘Cartesian circle’ and the dualistic theory of the mind and its relation to his theological and scientific views. Other chapters cover the philosophical implications of his work in algebra, his place in the seventeenth-century scientific revolution, the structure of his physics, and his work on physiology and psychology.


Read more...

La Criée : périodiques en ligne

La Criée : périodiques en ligne

Listing works and scientifical journals in various subjects and languages:



Read more...

XVIII Century Bibliography

A imagem “http://www.c18th.com/graphics/heads.gif” contém erros e não pode ser exibida.

Eighteenth Century Bibliography is a listing of texts that appeared between 1680 and 1810. Texts can be browsed by decade and author.

Read more...

La Mettrie - L´Homme Machine (1748/1921)

img212/7063/250pxjulienoffraydelametj3.jpg

La Mettrie, J (1748). L'homme machine; suivi de l'art de jouir, Introd. et notes de Maurice Solovine. Avec un portrait grave sur bois par Achille Ouvré (1921)

La Mettrie, J. Man A Machine. The Open Court Publishing Company (1943)

online editions here and here

Read more...

Revue philosophique de la France et de l'étranger (online editions)

link: cairn

Revue philosophique de la France et de l'étranger P.U.F. I.S.S.N. : papier 0035-3833 en ligne en cours 4 nos /an Site de la revue


--

2008/1 - Tome 133 - n° 1

Pascal, Machiavel, Hume, Freud

2007/4 - Tome 132 - n° 4

Philosophie des sciences : Auguste Comte

2007/3 - Tome 132 - n° 3

Geneviève Rodis-Lewis interprète de Descartes

2007/2 - Tome 132 - n° 2

Platon, Kant, Scheler

2007/1 - Tome 132 - n° 1

Hegel : la vie

2006/4 - Tome 131 - n° 4

Nietzsche

2006/3 - Tome 131 - n° 3

Gilbert Simondon

2006/2 - Tome 131 - n° 2

Vérités éternelles, forme de la langue, esthétique architecturales

2006/1 - Tome 131 - n° 1

Whitehead

2005/4 - Tome 130 - n° 4

La traduction philosophique

2005/3 - Tome 130 - n° 3

Ribot, Lévy-Bruhl, Durkheim

2005/2 - Tome 130 - n° 2

L'altérité

2005/1 - Tome 130 - n° 1

Écriture et persécution

2004/4 - Tome 129 - n° 4

La traduction philosophique

2004/3 - Tome 129 - n° 3

Philosophie du vivant

2004/2 - Tome 129 - n° 2

Tourner la phénoménologie

2004/1 - Tome 129 - n° 1

Marcel Conche

2003/4 - Tome 128 - n° 4

Le sublime et le terrible

2003/3 - Tome 128 - n° 3

Christian Wolff

2003/2 - Tome 128 - n° 2

Fénelon

2003/1 - Tome 128 - n° 1

Francis Bacon et l'invention

2002/4 - Tome 127 - n° 4

Autour de Heidegger

2002/3 - Tome 127 - n° 3

Philosopher en France (1940-1944)

2002/2 - Tome 127 - n° 2

Le temps dans l'Antiquité

2002/1 - Tome 127 - n° 1

Pascal

Religion, philosophie, psychanalyse
2001/4 - Tome 126 - n° 4

Psychanalyse, philosophie, religion

2001/3 - Tome 126 - n° 3

Michel Henry

Prochainement disponible
2001/2 - Tome 126 - n° 2

Hume

2001/1 - Tome 126 - n°1

Rationalité et automatisme


Read more...

Gary Banham - Kant´s Transcendental Imagination

Kant's Transcendental Imagination FREE Rapidshare Links for Download

Product Description
The role and place of transcendental psychology in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason has been a source of some contention. This work presents a detailed argument for restoring transcendental psychology to a central place in the interpretation of Kant’s Analytic, in the process providing a detailed response to more "austere" analytic readings.

About the Author
Gary Banham is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at Manchester Metropolitan University.

link

Read more...

Encyclopedia of the Human Brain

Encyclopedia of the Human Brain, Four Volume Set FREE Rapidshare Links for Download

Encyclopedia of the Human Brain, Four-Volume Set
Author: V. S. Ramachandran
Publisher: Academic Press
Edition: 1st edition (June 1, 2002)
Hardcover: 2616 pages

Summary:
In the past decade, enormous strides have been made in understanding the human brain. The advent of sophisticated new imaging techniques (e.g. PET, MRI, MEG, etc.) and new behavioral testing procedures have revolutionized our understanding of the brain, and we now know more about the anatomy, functions, and development of this organ than ever before. However, much of this knowledge is scattered across scientific journals and books in a diverse group of specialties: psychology, neuroscience, medicine, etc. The Encyclopedia of the Human Brain places all information in a single source and contains clearly written summaries on what is known of the human brain.

Covering anatomy, physiology, neuropsychology, clinical neurology, neuropharmacology, evolutionary biology, genetics, and behavioral science, this four-volume encyclopedia contains over 200 peer reviewed signed articles from experts around the world. The Encyclopedia articles range in size from 5-30 printed pages each, and contain a definition paragraph, glossary, outline, and suggested readings, in addition to the body of the article. Lavishly illustrated, the Encyclopedia includes over 1000 figures, many in full color. Managing both breadth and depth, the Encyclopedia is a must-have reference work for life science libraries and researchers investigating the human brain.

Encyclopedia of the Human Brain vol.1 to 4.pdf 77MB
All 4 volumes compiled into a single PDF and so fully searchable.

link

Read more...

Michel Foucault, "Security, Territory, Population Lectures at the College De France"

Michel Foucault, "Security, Territory, Population Lectures at the College De France"
384 pages | PDF | Publisher: Palgrave Macmillan; Tra edition (May 1, 2007) | English | ISBN: 1403986525 | 3.86 MB

This new title in the Collge de France Lecture Series charts a new development in Michel Foucault's thinking. Starting from the notion of 'bio-power' developed in the previous 1976 course, Society Must be Defended, Foucault explores the birth of the modern nation state in the Eighteenth Century through an analysis of its adminstration of institutionalized power relations, beginning with the fundamental techgies of security.

Review
"The English translation of Security, Territory and Population is a major event not only for Anglophone readers of Foucault’s work, but for all those concerned with understanding our present social and political condition. These lectures show that the trenchant analysis of biopower, “power over life”, which Foucault had begun in the first volume of the History of Sexuality and which he pursues here in terms of technologies of security, led him to a decisively deeper and more radical formulation of his guiding problematic—what he called “the government of the self and others”—the issue that would serve as the basis for all his subsequent work. Security, Territory and Population might thus properly be called the ‘missing link’ that reveals the underlying unity of Foucault’s later thought... Burchell’s translation is meticulous, supple, and attentive to the nuances of Foucault’s fluid lecture style. We all stand in his debt."-- Kevin Thompson, Book Review Editor, Continental Philosophy Review, Department of Philosophy, DePaul University, USA

"These lectures offer the wonderful opportunity of witnessing a great mind at work. In answering the question of whether the general economy of power in our societies is becoming a domain of security Foucault is never less than erudite, insightful and challenging. Here, probably better than anywhere else, we see the nature of his thoughts on nolothe rationality of modern government." -- Jeremy Jennings, Department of Politics, Queen Mary, University of London, and editor of The European Journal of Political Theory

"Security, Territory, Population' is a stunning display of Foucault's skills of historical research and theoretical insight. Exploring the emergence of 'bio-power'and the 'techniques of security' designed to shape and regulate populations from a distance, Foucault looks beyond disciplinary power to a distinctively modern form of government through freedom. Accessible and highly readable, these lectures have much to tell us about our contemporary situation." -- James Martin, Department of Politics, Goldsmiths, University of London

link to book

Read more...

Mitchell S. Green - “Self-Expression”

Mitchell S. Green “Self-Expression”

Oxford University Press, USA | 2008-01-10 | ISBN: 0199283788 | 256 pages | PDF | 1,4 Mb

Mitchell S. Green presents a systematic philosophical study of self-expression - a pervasive phenomenon of the everyday life of humans and other species, which has received scant attention in its own right. He explores the ways in which self-expression reveals our states of thought, feeling,
and experience, and he defends striking new theses concerning a wide range of fascinating topics: our ability to perceive emotion in others, artistic expression, empathy, expressive language, meaning, facial expression, and speech acts. He draws on insights from evolutionary game theory, ethology,
the philosophy of language, social psychology, pragmatics, aesthetics, and neuroscience to present a stimulating and accessible interdisciplinary work.

link

Read more...

Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence

Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence

Temporal Logic
Springer | 1995-09-30 | ISBN:0792335864 | 428 pages | PDF | 14,5 MB


Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence thus interweaves linguistic, philosophical and computational aspects into an informative and inspiring whole.

link to ebook

Read more...

Daniel H. Frank & Oliver Leaman - The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy

The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy

Daniel H. Frank & Oliver Leaman, “The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy” (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy)
Cambridge University Press (2003) | English | ISBN 0521655749 | 484 pages | PDF | 1.87 MB

Influenced originally by Islamic theological speculation, classical philosophers and Christian Scholasticism of the Middle Ages, Jewish thinkers living in Islamic and Christian lands philosophized about Judaism from the ninth to fifteenth centuries. They reflected on the nature of language about God, the creation of the world, the possibility of human freedom and the relationship between divine and human law. This Companion presents major medieval Jewish thinkers in a comprehensive introduction to a vital period of Jewish intellectual history.

link to download ebook

Read more...

C. T. R. Hayward - Interpretations of the Name Israel in Ancient Judaism and Some Early Christian Writings

Interpretations of the Name Israel

C. T. R. Hayward, “Interpretations of the Name Israel in Ancient Judaism and Some Early Christian Writings: From Victorious Athlete to Heavenly Champion”
Oxford University Press (2005) | English | ISBN 0199242372 | 422 pages | PDF | 1.84 MB
Ancient peoples regarded names as indicative of character and destiny. The Jews were no exception. This is a critical study of ancient exegesis of the title ‘Israel’ and the meanings attributed to it among Jews down to Talmudic times, along with some early Christian materials. C. T. R. Hayward explores ancient etymologies of ‘Israel’, and the utilization of these very varied explanations of the name in sustained works of exegesis like Jubilees; the writings of Ben Sira, Philo, and Josephus; and selected Rabbinic texts including Aramaic Targumim. He also examines translational works like the Septuagint, to illuminate those writings’ sense of what it meant to be a Jew.

link to download ebook

Read more...

Mark A. Bedau, Paul Humphreys - Emergence: Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science


Mark A. Bedau, Paul Humphreys “Emergence:
Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science (Bradford Books)"

The MIT Press | 2008-04-30 | ISBN: 026202621X | 482 pages | PDF | 4 Mb

Emergence, largely ignored just thirty years ago, has become one of the liveliest areas of research in both philosophy and science. Fueled by advances in complexity theory, artificial life, physics, psychology, sociology, and biology and by the parallel development of new conceptual tools in philosophy, the idea of emergence offers a way to understand a wide variety of complex phenomena in ways that are intriguingly different from more traditional approaches. This reader collects for the first time in one easily accessible place classic writings on emergence from contemporary philosophy and science. The chapters, by such prominent scholars as John Searle, Stephen Weinberg, William Wimsatt, Thomas Schelling, Jaegwon Kim, Robert Laughlin, Daniel Dennett, Herbert Simon, Stephen Wolfram, Jerry Fodor, Philip Anderson, and David Chalmers, cover the major approaches to emergence. Each of the three sections ("Philosophical Perspectives," "Scientific Perspectives," and "Background and Polemics") begins with an introduction putting the chapters into context and posing key questions for further exploration. A bibliography lists more specialized material, and an associated website (http://mitpress.mit.edu/emergence) links to downloadable software and to other sites and publications about emergence.

link to download ebook

Read more...

Titchener - Systematic Psychology: Prolegomena (original 1929 edition)

Titchener, Edward Bradford. Systematic Psychology: Prolegomena. MacMillan, 1929 (link to pdf file on archive, and and image visualization on questia)

CONTENTS




INTRODUCTION BRENTANO AND WUNDT: EMPIRICAL AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY
1. Wundt and Brentano as Representatives of Two Conceptions of Psychology 3
2. Resemblances between the Two Systems 6
3. Differences between the Two Systems 8
4. Brentano's Psychology in 1874 11
5. Wundt's Psychology in 1874 14
6. The Alternative 19

CHAPTER I SCIENCE
1. The Problem of Definition 25
2. The Scientific Temper 28
3. The Man of Science 30
4. The Classification of the Sciences 34
5. The Special Method of Science 38
6. Experimentation in Science 41
7. Science and Logic 45
8. Charles Darwin as Typical Man of Science 49
9. Science in Its Institutional Form 55
10. The Problem of Science 58
11. Science as Description 62
12. Applied Science or Technology 65



13. Summary 69
14. The Unification of the Sciences 73
15. Science in Education 77
16. Scientific Psychology 81

CHAPTER II THE DEFINITION OF PSYCHOLOGY: POINT OF VIEW
1. The Problem of Defining a Science 87
2. Thomson and Tait's Definition of Physics 92
3. Thomson's Definition of Biology 95
4. Wundt's Definition of Psychology and Natural Science 98
5. Wundt's Doctrine of Causation and Teleology 103
6. Critique of Wundt 106
7. Avenarius' Definition of Psychology and Physics 113
8. Definitions of Psychology by Mach, Ward, Külpe, Ebbinghaus, and James 119
9. The Definition of Psychology by Point of View 133
10. A Proposed Definition of Biology by Point of View 138
11. Psychology, Biology, and Physics as Three Coördinate Sciences 141

CHAPTER III THE DEFINITION OF PSYCHOLOGY: SUBJECT-MATTER
1. Introduction 147
2. Definition by Enumeration 148
3. "Inner" and "Outer" Worlds 151
4. Definition by Absence of Extension 154
5. Functional Psychology and the Psychology of Act 157



6. Ladd's Psychology 161
7. Critique of Ladd 167
8. The Functional Systems in General 177
9. Brentano's Definition by Intentional Inexistence of an Object 193
10. Meinong's and Husserl's Criticism of Brentano 196
11. Münsterberg's Criticism 199
12. Stumpf's Doctrine of Psychical Functions 201
13. Lipps' Psychology 206
14. Husserl's Phenomenology 213
15. Messer's Psychology 219
16. Comparison of Messer's and Witasek's Systems 226
7. A Triple Test of Intentionalism 235
18. Critique of Intentionalism 251
19. Critique of Empirical Psychology 257
20. Formal and Material Definitions of Physics, Biology, and Psychology 259
21. A Final Word 268

INDEX 271

Read more...

Darwin - On the origin of species (1859) - First Edition

img396/3329/originspeciesgm3.jpg

Darwin, C. R. 1859. On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: John Murray. 1st edition, 1st issue.

REVISION HISTORY: Text prepared by John van Wyhe and Sue Asscher 2002, advertizements added 9.2006. RN2

NOTE: This is the first edition of Darwin's most famous work. It was published 24 November 1859.

See R. B. Freeman's bibliographical introduction.

Many contemporary reviews are available on Darwin Online, see Reviews on the Supplementary works page.

The copy scanned was kindly provided by The Balfour and Newton Libraries, Cambridge. As the spine and covers of this copy were not in good condition, the images of these and the brown end papers are scanned from a copy kindly lent by The Charles Darwin Trust.

Read more...

Annette Meyer - The Experience of Human Diversity and the Search for Unity.

A.Meyer, «The Experience of Human Diversity and the Search for Unity. Concepts of Mankind in the Late Enlightenment»,Cromohs, 8 (2003): 1-15,

The epoch-making upheaval in European epistemological and scientific tradition in the eighteenth century is commonly regarded as being brought about by a “change of experience” in contemporary society. The German historian Reinhart Koselleck took the analysis of the gradual separation between what he called the “space of experience” and the “horizon of expectation” as the starting point for his definition of modernity, the origins of which he set between 1750 and 1850.[1] Likewise Michel Foucault, somewhat narrowing the period down around 1800, recognised these decades as the incubation period for the transformation of modern sciences.[2] In addition, the sociologist Wolf Lepenies diagnosed an enormous material growth in knowledge in the course of the eighteenth century which resulted in profound change in scientific methods of research and analysis. In particular Lepenies has pointed out the rise of the empirical imperative (Empirisierungszwang) mainly due to the pressure of ever expanding experience and observation (Erfahrungsdruck).[3]
What led to this fundamental change of experience which no longer followed the traditional patterns of explanation and no longer cherished the time-honoured sources of knowledge, including - above all of course - the Bible? And who was affected by the general change of experience?
Whilst an answer to these questions should start with analysing the ground-breaking discoveries in the natural sciences of the seventeenth century, it is also vital to take tho most general popularization of “knowledge” in the course of the eighteenth century into account. This popularization proceeded at different paces in different countries, but the general process was marked by a democratization in the access to “knowledge”. Typical exemples of this process of of this democratization include the opening of private libraries to the public, the foundation of academies, clubs and societies, all of which were important moments in the “structural transformation of the public sphere”.[4] The possibility of gaining new experiences, whether through the test-tube or through travel accounts, was no longer reserved to small academic circles; through the “revolution of print”, in quote Robert Darnton, such indirect experiences reached an increasingly broader readership, a process that has also been described as a revolution through reading.[5] Studies of the many newly established public libraries show that travel accounts were at the top of the list of requested books. The information concerning foreign peoples – and especially the study of the so-called “savages” - became a matter of broad public discussion, whereas up until then it had only been debated in small specialist circles.[6]

Read more...

Haller Bern - Versuch einer Anthropologie oder Philosophie des Menschen nach seinen körperlichen Anlagen (Johan Ith, 1794-95)

Read more...

Hardt, M. - Gilles Deleuze - An Apprenticeship in Philosophy.

img117/5038/0816621616bigxc3.gif


Hardt, M. Gilles Deleuze - An Apprenticeship in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993 [link]



Introduction

Hegel and the Foundations of Poststructuralism

Continental poststructuralism has problematized the foundations of philosophical and political thought. Perhaps dazzled by the impact of this theoretical rupture, diverse American authors have embraced this movement as the inauguration of a postphilosophical culture where philosophical claims and political judgments admit no justification and rest on no foundation. This problematic, however, settles too easily into a new opposition that obscures the real possibilities afforded by contemporary Continental theory. At the hands of both its supporters and its detractors, poststructuralism has been incorporated into a series of Anglo-American debates-between modernists and postmodernists, between communitarians and liberals-in such a way as to misdirect and blunt its force. The importance of poststructuralism cannot be captured by posing a new series of oppositions, but only by recognizing the nuances and alternatives it proposes within modernity, within the philosophical tradition, within the contemporary field of social practices. If we look closely at the historical development of poststructuralist thought, at the complex social and theoretical pressures it encountered and the tools it constructed to face them, we can recapture some of its critical and constructive powers. Poststructuralism, we find, is not oriented simply toward the negation of theoretical foundations, but rather toward the exploration of new grounds for philosophical and political inquiry; it is involved not simply in the rejection of the tradition of political and philosophical discourse, but more importantly in the articulation and affirmation of alternative lineages that arise from within the tradition itself.

The roots of poststructuralism and its unifying basis lie, in large part, in a general opposition not to the philosophical tradition tout court but specifically to the Hegelian tradition. For the generation of Continental thinkers that came to maturity in the 1960s, Hegel was the figure of order and authority that served as the focus of antagonism. Deleuze speaks for his entire cohort: “What I detested above all was Hegelianism and the dialectic” (“Lettre à Michel Cressole” 110). In order to appreciate this antagonism, however, we must realize that, in the domain of Continental theory during this period, Hegel was ubiquitous. As a result of influential interpretations by theorists as diverse as Kojève, Gramsci, Sartre, and Bobbio, Hegel had come to dominate the theoretical horizon as the ineluctable centerpiece of philosophical speculation, social theory, and political practice. In 1968, it appeared to François Châtelet that every philosopher had to begin with Hegel: “[Hegel] determined a horizon, a language, a code that we are still at the very heart of today. Hegel, by this fact, is our Plato: the one who delimits-ideologically or scientifically, positively or negatively-the theoretical possibilities of theory” (Hegel 2). Any account of Continental poststructuralism must take this framework of generalized Hegelianism as its point of departure.

The first problem of poststructuralism, then, is how to evade a Hegelian foundation. In order to understand the extent of this problem, however, we have to recognize the serious restrictions facing such a project in the specific social and historical context. Châtelet argues, in curiously dialectical fashion, that the only viable project to counter Hegelianism is to make Hegel the negative foundation of philosophy. Those who neglect the initial step of addressing and actively rejecting Hegel, he claims, those who attempt simply to turn their backs on Hegel, run the risk of ending up as mere repetitions of the Hegelian problematic. “Certainly, there are many contemporary philosophical projects that ignore Hegelianism…. They are dealing with the false meaning of absolute beginnings, and, moreover, they deprive themselves of a good point of support. It is better-like Marx and Nietzsche-to begin with Hegel than to end up with him” (4). Hegelianism was such a powerful vortex that in attempting to ignore it one would inevitably be sucked in by its power. Only anti-Hegelianism provided the negative point of support necessary for a post-Hegelian or even a non-Hegelian project.

From this point of view, the early works of Gilles Deleuze are exemplary of the entire generation of poststructuralist thinkers. In his early investigations into the history of philosophy we can see an intense concentration of the generalized anti-Hegelianism of the time. Deleuze attempted to confront Hegeland dialectical thought head-on, as Châtelet said one must, with a rigorous philosophical refutation; he engaged Hegelianism not in order to salvage its worthwhile elements, not to extract “the rational kernel from the mystical shell, ” but rather to articulate a total critique and a rejection of the negative dialectical framework so as to achieve a real autonomy, a theoretical separation from the entire Hegelian problematic. The philosophers that Deleuze selects as partisans in this struggle (Bergson, Nietzsche, and Spinoza) appear to allow him successive steps toward the realization of this project. Many recent critics of French poststructuralism, however, have charged that the poststructuralists did not understand Hegel and, with a facile anti-Hegelianism, missed the most powerful thrust of his thought. 1 Deleuze is the most important example to consider in this regard because he mounts the most focused and precise attack on Hegelianism. Nonetheless, perhaps since this cultural and philosophical paradigm was so tenacious, the attempted deracination from the Hegelian terrain is not immediately successful. We find that Deleuze often poses his project not only in the traditional language of Hegelianism but also in terms of typical Hegelian problems-the determination of being, the unity of the One and the Multiple, and so on. Paradoxically, in his effort to establish Hegel as a negative foundation for his thought, Deleuze may appear to be very Hegelian.

If Hegelianism is the first problem of poststructuralism, then, anti-Hegelianism quickly presents itself as the second. In many respects, Hegelianism is the most difficult of adversaries because it possesses such an extraordinary capacity to recuperate opposition. Many Anglo-American authors, seeking to discount the rupture of Continental poststructuralism, have rightly emphasized this dilemma. Judith Butler presents the challenge for anti-Hegelians in very clear terms: “References to a 'break' with Hegel are almost always impossible, if only because Hegel has made the very notion of 'breaking with' into the central tenet of his dialectic” (Subjects of Desire 184). It may seem, then, from this perspective, that to be anti-Hegelian, through a dialectical twist, becomes a position more Hegelian than ever; in effect, one might claim that the effort to be an “other” to Hegel can always be folded into an “other” within Hegel. There is in fact a growing literature that extends this line of argument, claiming that the work of contemporary anti-Hegelians consists merely in unconscious repetitions of Hegelian dramas without the power of the Hegelian subject and the rigor and clarity of the Hegelian logic. 2

The problem of recuperation that faces the anti-Hegelian foundation of poststructuralism offers a second and more important explanation for our selection of Deleuze in this study Although numerous authors have made important contributions to our critique of Hegel, Deleuze has gone the furthest in extricating himself from the problems of anti-Hegelianism and constructing an alternative terrain for thought-no longer post-Hegelian but rather separate from the problem of Hegel. If our first reason for proposing Deleuze as an exemplary poststructuralist thinker was that he is representative of the antagonism to Hegelianism, our second is that he is anomalous in his extension of that project away from Hegel toward a separate, alternative terrain. There are two central elements of this passage that Deleuze develops in different registers and on different planes of thought: a nondialectical conception of negation and a constitutive theory of practice. We cannot understand these elements, I repeat, if we merely oppose them to Hegelian conceptions of negation and practice. We must recognize their nuances and pose them on an alternative plane. These two themes, then, negation and practice, understood with their new forms, comprise the foundation of the new terrain that post-structuralism has to offer for philosophical and political thought, a terrain for contemporary research.

Let us briefly examine the general outlines of these two central elements of Deleuze's project. The concept of negation that lies at the center of dialectical thought seems to pose the most serious challenge for any theory that claims to be anti- or post-Hegelian. “Nondialectical difference, ” Judith Butler writes, “despite its various forms, is the labor of the negative which has lost its 'magic'” (184). The nondialectical concept of negation that we find in Deleuze's total critique certainly contains none of the magical effect of the dialectic. The dialectical negation is always directed toward the miracle of resurrection: It is a negation “which supersedes in such a way as to preserve and maintain what is superseded, and consequently survives its own supersession” (Phenomenology of Spirit §188). Nondialectical negation is more simple and more absolute. With no faith in the beyond, in the eventual resurrection, negation becomes an extreme moment of nihilism: In Hegelian terms, it points to the death of the other. Hegel considers this pure death, “the absolute Lord, ” merely an abstract conception of negation; in the contemporary world, however, the absolute character of negation has become dreadfully concrete, and the magical resurrection implicit in the dialectical negation appears merely as superstition. Nondialectical negation is absolute not in the sense that everything present is negated but in that what is negated is attacked with full, unrestrained force. On the one hand, authors like Deleuze propose this nondialectical concept of negation not in the promotion of nihilism, but merely as the recognition of an element of our world. We can situate this theoretical position in relation to the field of “nuclear criticism, ” but not in the sense that nuclear weapons pose the threat of negation, not in the sense that they pose the universal fear of death: This is merely the “standing negation” of a Hegelian framework, preserving the given order. The negation of the bomb is nondialectical in its actuality, not in the planning rooms of Washington but in the streets of Hiroshima, as an agent of total destruction. There is nothing positive in the nondialectical negation, no magical resurrection: It is pure. On the other hand, with an eye toward the philosophical tradition, we can locate this radical conception of negation in the methodological proposals of certain Scholastic authors such as Roger Bacon. The pure negation is the first moment of a precritical conception of critique: pars destruens, pars construens. The important characteristics are the purity and autonomy of the two critical moments. Negation clears the terrain for creation; it is a bipartite sequence that precludes any third, synthetic moment. Thus we can at least gesture toward solid grounds for this radical, nondialectical negation: It is as new as the destructive force of contemporary warfare and as old as the precritical skepticism of the Scholastics.

The radicality of negation forces Deleuze to engage questions of the lowest order, questions of the nature of being. Deleuze's total critique involves a destruction so absolute that it becomes necessary to question what makes reality possible. We should emphasize that, on one hand, the rejection of Hegelian ontology does not lead Deleuze to some form of deontological thought. Although he denies any preconstituted structure of being or any ideological order of existence, Deleuze still operates on the highest planes of ontological speculation. Once again, to reject Hegelian ontology is not to reject ontology tout court. Deleuze insists instead on alternatives within the ontological tradition. On the other hand, however, we should be careful from the outset to distinguish this from a Heideggerian return to ontology, most importantly because Deleuze will only accept “superficial” responses to the question “What makes being possible?” In other words, he limits us to a strictly immanent and materialist ontological discourse that refuses any deep or hidden foundation of being. There is nothing veiled or negative about Deleuze's being; it is fully expressed in the world. Being, in this sense, is superficial, positive, and full. Deleuze refuses any “intellectualist” account of being, any account that in any way subordinates being to thought, that poses thinking as the supreme form of being. 3 There are numerous contributions to this project of a materialist ontology throughout the history of philosophy-such as Spinoza, Marx, Nietzsche, and Lucretius-and we will refer to them in our discussion to provide illustrative points of reference. We will focus, however, on Deleuze's constitutive conception of practice as a foundation of ontology. The radical negation of the nondialectical pars destruens emphasizes that no preconstituted order is available to define the organization of being. Practice provides the terms for a material pars construens; practice is what makes the constitution of being possible. The investigation of the nature of power allows Deleuze to bring substance to the materialist discourse and to raise the theory of practice to the level of ontology. The foundation of being, then, resides both on a corporeal and on a mental plane, in the complex dynamics of behavior, in the superficial interactions of bodies. This is not an Althusserian “theoretical practice, ” but rather a more practical conception of practice, autonomous of any “theoricist tendency, ” a “practical practice” that is oriented principally toward the ontological rather than the epistemological realm. The only nature available to ontological discourse is an absolutely artificial conception of nature, a hybrid nature, a nature produced in practice-further removed than a second nature, an nth nature. This approach to ontology is as new as the infinitely plastic universe of cyborgs and as old as the tradition of materialist philosophy. What will be important throughout our discussion is that the traditionally fundamental terms-such as necessity, reason, nature, and being-though shaken from their transcendental fixity, still serve as a foundation because they acquire a certain consistency and substance in our world. Being, now historicized and materialized, is delimited by the outer bounds of the contemporary imagination, of the contemporary field of practice.

I elaborate these conceptions of nondialectical negation and constitutive practice in Deleuze's work by reading the evolution of his thought, that is, by following the progression of critical questions that guide his investigations during successive periods. The evolution of Deleuze's thought unfolds as he directs his attention sequentially to a series of authors in the philosophical canon and poses them each a specific question. His work on Bergson offers a critique of negative ontology and proposes in its stead an absolutely positive movement of being that rests on an efficient and internal notion of causality. To the negative movement of determination, he opposes the positive movement of differentiation; to the dialectical unity of the One and the Multiple, he opposes the irreducible multiplicity of becoming. The question of the organization or the constitution of the world, however, of the being of becoming, pushes Deleuze to pose these ontological issues in ethical terms. Nietzsche allows him to transpose the results of ontological speculation to an ethical horizon, to the field of forces, of sense and value, where the positive movement of being becomes the affirmation of being. The thematic of power in Nietzsche provides the theoretical passage that links Bergsonian ontology to an ethics of active expression. Spinoza covers this same passage and extends it to practice. Just as Nietzsche poses the affirmation of speculation, Spinoza poses the affirmation of practice, or joy, at the center of ontology. Deleuze argues that Spinoza's is an ontological conception of practice; Spinoza conceives practice, that is, as constitutive of being. In the precritical world of Spinoza's practical philosophy, Deleuze's thought finally discovers a real autonomy from the Hegelian problematic.

One lesson to be learned from this philosophical project is to highlight the nuances that define an antagonism. Once we stop clouding the issue with crude oppositions and recognize instead the specificity of an antagonism, we can begin to bring out finer nuances in our terminology. For example, when I pose the question of the foundations of poststructuralist thought I mean to contest the claim that this thought is properly characterized as antifoundationalism. To pose the issue as an exclusive opposition is, in effect, to credit the enemy with too much force, with too much theoretical terrain. Poststructuralism does critique a certain notion of foundation, but only to affirm another notion that is more adequate to its ends. Against a transcendental foundation we find an immanent one; against a given, teleological foundation we find a material, open one. 4 A similar nuance must be made in our discussion of causality. When we look closely at Deleuze's critique of causality we find not only a powerful rejection of the final cause and the formal cause, but also an equally powerful affirmation of the efficient cause as central to his philosophical project. Deleuze's ontology draws on the tradition of causal arguments and develops notions of both being's “productivity” and its “producibility, ” that is, of its aptitudes to produce and to be produced. I will argue that efficient causality, in fact, provides a key to a coherent account of Deleuze's entire discourse on difference. The nuances in the use of “foundation” and “causality” are perhaps best summarized by the distinction between order and organization. By the order of being, of truth, or of society I intend the structure imposed as necessary and eternal from above, from outside the material scene of forces; I use organization, on the other hand, to designate the coordination and accumulation of accidental (in the philosophical sense, i.e., nonnecessary) encounters and developments from below, from within the immanent field of forces. In other words, I do not conceive of organization as a blueprint of development or as the projected vision of an avant-garde, but rather as an immanent creation or composition of a relationship of consistency and coordination. In this sense, organization, the composition of creative forces, is always an art.

Throughout this study we will encounter unresolved problems and propositions that are powerfully suggestive but perhaps not clearly and rigorously delimited. We do not look to Deleuze here, however, simply to find the solutions to contemporary theoretical problems. More important, we inquire into his thought in order to investigate the proposals of a new problematic for research after the poststructuralist rupture, to test our footing on a terrain where new grounds of philosophical and political thought are possible. What we ask of Deleuze, above all, is to teach us the contemporary possibilities of philosophy.

Read more...

Blog Archive

Lorem Ipsum

"All testing, all confirmation and disconfirmation of a hypothesis takes place already within a system. And this system is not a more or less arbitrary and doubtful point of departure for all our arguments; no it belongs to the essence of what we call an argument. The system is not so much the point of departure, as the element in which our arguments have their life."
- Wittgenstein

Lorem Ipsum

"Le poète ne retient pas ce qu’il découvre ; l’ayant transcrit, le perd bientôt. En cela réside sa nouveauté, son infini et son péril"

René Char, La Bibliothèque est en feu (1956)


  © Blogger template Shush by Ourblogtemplates.com 2009

Back to TOP