Mitchell S. Green - “Self-Expression”

Mitchell S. Green “Self-Expression”

Oxford University Press, USA | 2008-01-10 | ISBN: 0199283788 | 256 pages | PDF | 1,4 Mb

Mitchell S. Green presents a systematic philosophical study of self-expression - a pervasive phenomenon of the everyday life of humans and other species, which has received scant attention in its own right. He explores the ways in which self-expression reveals our states of thought, feeling,
and experience, and he defends striking new theses concerning a wide range of fascinating topics: our ability to perceive emotion in others, artistic expression, empathy, expressive language, meaning, facial expression, and speech acts. He draws on insights from evolutionary game theory, ethology,
the philosophy of language, social psychology, pragmatics, aesthetics, and neuroscience to present a stimulating and accessible interdisciplinary work.

link

Read more...

Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence

Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence

Temporal Logic
Springer | 1995-09-30 | ISBN:0792335864 | 428 pages | PDF | 14,5 MB


Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intelligence thus interweaves linguistic, philosophical and computational aspects into an informative and inspiring whole.

link to ebook

Read more...

Daniel H. Frank & Oliver Leaman - The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy

The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy

Daniel H. Frank & Oliver Leaman, “The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy” (Cambridge Companions to Philosophy)
Cambridge University Press (2003) | English | ISBN 0521655749 | 484 pages | PDF | 1.87 MB

Influenced originally by Islamic theological speculation, classical philosophers and Christian Scholasticism of the Middle Ages, Jewish thinkers living in Islamic and Christian lands philosophized about Judaism from the ninth to fifteenth centuries. They reflected on the nature of language about God, the creation of the world, the possibility of human freedom and the relationship between divine and human law. This Companion presents major medieval Jewish thinkers in a comprehensive introduction to a vital period of Jewish intellectual history.

link to download ebook

Read more...

C. T. R. Hayward - Interpretations of the Name Israel in Ancient Judaism and Some Early Christian Writings

Interpretations of the Name Israel

C. T. R. Hayward, “Interpretations of the Name Israel in Ancient Judaism and Some Early Christian Writings: From Victorious Athlete to Heavenly Champion”
Oxford University Press (2005) | English | ISBN 0199242372 | 422 pages | PDF | 1.84 MB
Ancient peoples regarded names as indicative of character and destiny. The Jews were no exception. This is a critical study of ancient exegesis of the title ‘Israel’ and the meanings attributed to it among Jews down to Talmudic times, along with some early Christian materials. C. T. R. Hayward explores ancient etymologies of ‘Israel’, and the utilization of these very varied explanations of the name in sustained works of exegesis like Jubilees; the writings of Ben Sira, Philo, and Josephus; and selected Rabbinic texts including Aramaic Targumim. He also examines translational works like the Septuagint, to illuminate those writings’ sense of what it meant to be a Jew.

link to download ebook

Read more...

Mark A. Bedau, Paul Humphreys - Emergence: Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science


Mark A. Bedau, Paul Humphreys “Emergence:
Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science (Bradford Books)"

The MIT Press | 2008-04-30 | ISBN: 026202621X | 482 pages | PDF | 4 Mb

Emergence, largely ignored just thirty years ago, has become one of the liveliest areas of research in both philosophy and science. Fueled by advances in complexity theory, artificial life, physics, psychology, sociology, and biology and by the parallel development of new conceptual tools in philosophy, the idea of emergence offers a way to understand a wide variety of complex phenomena in ways that are intriguingly different from more traditional approaches. This reader collects for the first time in one easily accessible place classic writings on emergence from contemporary philosophy and science. The chapters, by such prominent scholars as John Searle, Stephen Weinberg, William Wimsatt, Thomas Schelling, Jaegwon Kim, Robert Laughlin, Daniel Dennett, Herbert Simon, Stephen Wolfram, Jerry Fodor, Philip Anderson, and David Chalmers, cover the major approaches to emergence. Each of the three sections ("Philosophical Perspectives," "Scientific Perspectives," and "Background and Polemics") begins with an introduction putting the chapters into context and posing key questions for further exploration. A bibliography lists more specialized material, and an associated website (http://mitpress.mit.edu/emergence) links to downloadable software and to other sites and publications about emergence.

link to download ebook

Read more...

Titchener - Systematic Psychology: Prolegomena (original 1929 edition)

Titchener, Edward Bradford. Systematic Psychology: Prolegomena. MacMillan, 1929 (link to pdf file on archive, and and image visualization on questia)

CONTENTS




INTRODUCTION BRENTANO AND WUNDT: EMPIRICAL AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY
1. Wundt and Brentano as Representatives of Two Conceptions of Psychology 3
2. Resemblances between the Two Systems 6
3. Differences between the Two Systems 8
4. Brentano's Psychology in 1874 11
5. Wundt's Psychology in 1874 14
6. The Alternative 19

CHAPTER I SCIENCE
1. The Problem of Definition 25
2. The Scientific Temper 28
3. The Man of Science 30
4. The Classification of the Sciences 34
5. The Special Method of Science 38
6. Experimentation in Science 41
7. Science and Logic 45
8. Charles Darwin as Typical Man of Science 49
9. Science in Its Institutional Form 55
10. The Problem of Science 58
11. Science as Description 62
12. Applied Science or Technology 65



13. Summary 69
14. The Unification of the Sciences 73
15. Science in Education 77
16. Scientific Psychology 81

CHAPTER II THE DEFINITION OF PSYCHOLOGY: POINT OF VIEW
1. The Problem of Defining a Science 87
2. Thomson and Tait's Definition of Physics 92
3. Thomson's Definition of Biology 95
4. Wundt's Definition of Psychology and Natural Science 98
5. Wundt's Doctrine of Causation and Teleology 103
6. Critique of Wundt 106
7. Avenarius' Definition of Psychology and Physics 113
8. Definitions of Psychology by Mach, Ward, Külpe, Ebbinghaus, and James 119
9. The Definition of Psychology by Point of View 133
10. A Proposed Definition of Biology by Point of View 138
11. Psychology, Biology, and Physics as Three Coördinate Sciences 141

CHAPTER III THE DEFINITION OF PSYCHOLOGY: SUBJECT-MATTER
1. Introduction 147
2. Definition by Enumeration 148
3. "Inner" and "Outer" Worlds 151
4. Definition by Absence of Extension 154
5. Functional Psychology and the Psychology of Act 157



6. Ladd's Psychology 161
7. Critique of Ladd 167
8. The Functional Systems in General 177
9. Brentano's Definition by Intentional Inexistence of an Object 193
10. Meinong's and Husserl's Criticism of Brentano 196
11. Münsterberg's Criticism 199
12. Stumpf's Doctrine of Psychical Functions 201
13. Lipps' Psychology 206
14. Husserl's Phenomenology 213
15. Messer's Psychology 219
16. Comparison of Messer's and Witasek's Systems 226
7. A Triple Test of Intentionalism 235
18. Critique of Intentionalism 251
19. Critique of Empirical Psychology 257
20. Formal and Material Definitions of Physics, Biology, and Psychology 259
21. A Final Word 268

INDEX 271

Read more...

Darwin - On the origin of species (1859) - First Edition

img396/3329/originspeciesgm3.jpg

Darwin, C. R. 1859. On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: John Murray. 1st edition, 1st issue.

REVISION HISTORY: Text prepared by John van Wyhe and Sue Asscher 2002, advertizements added 9.2006. RN2

NOTE: This is the first edition of Darwin's most famous work. It was published 24 November 1859.

See R. B. Freeman's bibliographical introduction.

Many contemporary reviews are available on Darwin Online, see Reviews on the Supplementary works page.

The copy scanned was kindly provided by The Balfour and Newton Libraries, Cambridge. As the spine and covers of this copy were not in good condition, the images of these and the brown end papers are scanned from a copy kindly lent by The Charles Darwin Trust.

Read more...

Annette Meyer - The Experience of Human Diversity and the Search for Unity.

A.Meyer, «The Experience of Human Diversity and the Search for Unity. Concepts of Mankind in the Late Enlightenment»,Cromohs, 8 (2003): 1-15,

The epoch-making upheaval in European epistemological and scientific tradition in the eighteenth century is commonly regarded as being brought about by a “change of experience” in contemporary society. The German historian Reinhart Koselleck took the analysis of the gradual separation between what he called the “space of experience” and the “horizon of expectation” as the starting point for his definition of modernity, the origins of which he set between 1750 and 1850.[1] Likewise Michel Foucault, somewhat narrowing the period down around 1800, recognised these decades as the incubation period for the transformation of modern sciences.[2] In addition, the sociologist Wolf Lepenies diagnosed an enormous material growth in knowledge in the course of the eighteenth century which resulted in profound change in scientific methods of research and analysis. In particular Lepenies has pointed out the rise of the empirical imperative (Empirisierungszwang) mainly due to the pressure of ever expanding experience and observation (Erfahrungsdruck).[3]
What led to this fundamental change of experience which no longer followed the traditional patterns of explanation and no longer cherished the time-honoured sources of knowledge, including - above all of course - the Bible? And who was affected by the general change of experience?
Whilst an answer to these questions should start with analysing the ground-breaking discoveries in the natural sciences of the seventeenth century, it is also vital to take tho most general popularization of “knowledge” in the course of the eighteenth century into account. This popularization proceeded at different paces in different countries, but the general process was marked by a democratization in the access to “knowledge”. Typical exemples of this process of of this democratization include the opening of private libraries to the public, the foundation of academies, clubs and societies, all of which were important moments in the “structural transformation of the public sphere”.[4] The possibility of gaining new experiences, whether through the test-tube or through travel accounts, was no longer reserved to small academic circles; through the “revolution of print”, in quote Robert Darnton, such indirect experiences reached an increasingly broader readership, a process that has also been described as a revolution through reading.[5] Studies of the many newly established public libraries show that travel accounts were at the top of the list of requested books. The information concerning foreign peoples – and especially the study of the so-called “savages” - became a matter of broad public discussion, whereas up until then it had only been debated in small specialist circles.[6]

Read more...

Haller Bern - Versuch einer Anthropologie oder Philosophie des Menschen nach seinen körperlichen Anlagen (Johan Ith, 1794-95)

Read more...

Hardt, M. - Gilles Deleuze - An Apprenticeship in Philosophy.

img117/5038/0816621616bigxc3.gif


Hardt, M. Gilles Deleuze - An Apprenticeship in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993 [link]



Introduction

Hegel and the Foundations of Poststructuralism

Continental poststructuralism has problematized the foundations of philosophical and political thought. Perhaps dazzled by the impact of this theoretical rupture, diverse American authors have embraced this movement as the inauguration of a postphilosophical culture where philosophical claims and political judgments admit no justification and rest on no foundation. This problematic, however, settles too easily into a new opposition that obscures the real possibilities afforded by contemporary Continental theory. At the hands of both its supporters and its detractors, poststructuralism has been incorporated into a series of Anglo-American debates-between modernists and postmodernists, between communitarians and liberals-in such a way as to misdirect and blunt its force. The importance of poststructuralism cannot be captured by posing a new series of oppositions, but only by recognizing the nuances and alternatives it proposes within modernity, within the philosophical tradition, within the contemporary field of social practices. If we look closely at the historical development of poststructuralist thought, at the complex social and theoretical pressures it encountered and the tools it constructed to face them, we can recapture some of its critical and constructive powers. Poststructuralism, we find, is not oriented simply toward the negation of theoretical foundations, but rather toward the exploration of new grounds for philosophical and political inquiry; it is involved not simply in the rejection of the tradition of political and philosophical discourse, but more importantly in the articulation and affirmation of alternative lineages that arise from within the tradition itself.

The roots of poststructuralism and its unifying basis lie, in large part, in a general opposition not to the philosophical tradition tout court but specifically to the Hegelian tradition. For the generation of Continental thinkers that came to maturity in the 1960s, Hegel was the figure of order and authority that served as the focus of antagonism. Deleuze speaks for his entire cohort: “What I detested above all was Hegelianism and the dialectic” (“Lettre à Michel Cressole” 110). In order to appreciate this antagonism, however, we must realize that, in the domain of Continental theory during this period, Hegel was ubiquitous. As a result of influential interpretations by theorists as diverse as Kojève, Gramsci, Sartre, and Bobbio, Hegel had come to dominate the theoretical horizon as the ineluctable centerpiece of philosophical speculation, social theory, and political practice. In 1968, it appeared to François Châtelet that every philosopher had to begin with Hegel: “[Hegel] determined a horizon, a language, a code that we are still at the very heart of today. Hegel, by this fact, is our Plato: the one who delimits-ideologically or scientifically, positively or negatively-the theoretical possibilities of theory” (Hegel 2). Any account of Continental poststructuralism must take this framework of generalized Hegelianism as its point of departure.

The first problem of poststructuralism, then, is how to evade a Hegelian foundation. In order to understand the extent of this problem, however, we have to recognize the serious restrictions facing such a project in the specific social and historical context. Châtelet argues, in curiously dialectical fashion, that the only viable project to counter Hegelianism is to make Hegel the negative foundation of philosophy. Those who neglect the initial step of addressing and actively rejecting Hegel, he claims, those who attempt simply to turn their backs on Hegel, run the risk of ending up as mere repetitions of the Hegelian problematic. “Certainly, there are many contemporary philosophical projects that ignore Hegelianism…. They are dealing with the false meaning of absolute beginnings, and, moreover, they deprive themselves of a good point of support. It is better-like Marx and Nietzsche-to begin with Hegel than to end up with him” (4). Hegelianism was such a powerful vortex that in attempting to ignore it one would inevitably be sucked in by its power. Only anti-Hegelianism provided the negative point of support necessary for a post-Hegelian or even a non-Hegelian project.

From this point of view, the early works of Gilles Deleuze are exemplary of the entire generation of poststructuralist thinkers. In his early investigations into the history of philosophy we can see an intense concentration of the generalized anti-Hegelianism of the time. Deleuze attempted to confront Hegeland dialectical thought head-on, as Châtelet said one must, with a rigorous philosophical refutation; he engaged Hegelianism not in order to salvage its worthwhile elements, not to extract “the rational kernel from the mystical shell, ” but rather to articulate a total critique and a rejection of the negative dialectical framework so as to achieve a real autonomy, a theoretical separation from the entire Hegelian problematic. The philosophers that Deleuze selects as partisans in this struggle (Bergson, Nietzsche, and Spinoza) appear to allow him successive steps toward the realization of this project. Many recent critics of French poststructuralism, however, have charged that the poststructuralists did not understand Hegel and, with a facile anti-Hegelianism, missed the most powerful thrust of his thought. 1 Deleuze is the most important example to consider in this regard because he mounts the most focused and precise attack on Hegelianism. Nonetheless, perhaps since this cultural and philosophical paradigm was so tenacious, the attempted deracination from the Hegelian terrain is not immediately successful. We find that Deleuze often poses his project not only in the traditional language of Hegelianism but also in terms of typical Hegelian problems-the determination of being, the unity of the One and the Multiple, and so on. Paradoxically, in his effort to establish Hegel as a negative foundation for his thought, Deleuze may appear to be very Hegelian.

If Hegelianism is the first problem of poststructuralism, then, anti-Hegelianism quickly presents itself as the second. In many respects, Hegelianism is the most difficult of adversaries because it possesses such an extraordinary capacity to recuperate opposition. Many Anglo-American authors, seeking to discount the rupture of Continental poststructuralism, have rightly emphasized this dilemma. Judith Butler presents the challenge for anti-Hegelians in very clear terms: “References to a 'break' with Hegel are almost always impossible, if only because Hegel has made the very notion of 'breaking with' into the central tenet of his dialectic” (Subjects of Desire 184). It may seem, then, from this perspective, that to be anti-Hegelian, through a dialectical twist, becomes a position more Hegelian than ever; in effect, one might claim that the effort to be an “other” to Hegel can always be folded into an “other” within Hegel. There is in fact a growing literature that extends this line of argument, claiming that the work of contemporary anti-Hegelians consists merely in unconscious repetitions of Hegelian dramas without the power of the Hegelian subject and the rigor and clarity of the Hegelian logic. 2

The problem of recuperation that faces the anti-Hegelian foundation of poststructuralism offers a second and more important explanation for our selection of Deleuze in this study Although numerous authors have made important contributions to our critique of Hegel, Deleuze has gone the furthest in extricating himself from the problems of anti-Hegelianism and constructing an alternative terrain for thought-no longer post-Hegelian but rather separate from the problem of Hegel. If our first reason for proposing Deleuze as an exemplary poststructuralist thinker was that he is representative of the antagonism to Hegelianism, our second is that he is anomalous in his extension of that project away from Hegel toward a separate, alternative terrain. There are two central elements of this passage that Deleuze develops in different registers and on different planes of thought: a nondialectical conception of negation and a constitutive theory of practice. We cannot understand these elements, I repeat, if we merely oppose them to Hegelian conceptions of negation and practice. We must recognize their nuances and pose them on an alternative plane. These two themes, then, negation and practice, understood with their new forms, comprise the foundation of the new terrain that post-structuralism has to offer for philosophical and political thought, a terrain for contemporary research.

Let us briefly examine the general outlines of these two central elements of Deleuze's project. The concept of negation that lies at the center of dialectical thought seems to pose the most serious challenge for any theory that claims to be anti- or post-Hegelian. “Nondialectical difference, ” Judith Butler writes, “despite its various forms, is the labor of the negative which has lost its 'magic'” (184). The nondialectical concept of negation that we find in Deleuze's total critique certainly contains none of the magical effect of the dialectic. The dialectical negation is always directed toward the miracle of resurrection: It is a negation “which supersedes in such a way as to preserve and maintain what is superseded, and consequently survives its own supersession” (Phenomenology of Spirit §188). Nondialectical negation is more simple and more absolute. With no faith in the beyond, in the eventual resurrection, negation becomes an extreme moment of nihilism: In Hegelian terms, it points to the death of the other. Hegel considers this pure death, “the absolute Lord, ” merely an abstract conception of negation; in the contemporary world, however, the absolute character of negation has become dreadfully concrete, and the magical resurrection implicit in the dialectical negation appears merely as superstition. Nondialectical negation is absolute not in the sense that everything present is negated but in that what is negated is attacked with full, unrestrained force. On the one hand, authors like Deleuze propose this nondialectical concept of negation not in the promotion of nihilism, but merely as the recognition of an element of our world. We can situate this theoretical position in relation to the field of “nuclear criticism, ” but not in the sense that nuclear weapons pose the threat of negation, not in the sense that they pose the universal fear of death: This is merely the “standing negation” of a Hegelian framework, preserving the given order. The negation of the bomb is nondialectical in its actuality, not in the planning rooms of Washington but in the streets of Hiroshima, as an agent of total destruction. There is nothing positive in the nondialectical negation, no magical resurrection: It is pure. On the other hand, with an eye toward the philosophical tradition, we can locate this radical conception of negation in the methodological proposals of certain Scholastic authors such as Roger Bacon. The pure negation is the first moment of a precritical conception of critique: pars destruens, pars construens. The important characteristics are the purity and autonomy of the two critical moments. Negation clears the terrain for creation; it is a bipartite sequence that precludes any third, synthetic moment. Thus we can at least gesture toward solid grounds for this radical, nondialectical negation: It is as new as the destructive force of contemporary warfare and as old as the precritical skepticism of the Scholastics.

The radicality of negation forces Deleuze to engage questions of the lowest order, questions of the nature of being. Deleuze's total critique involves a destruction so absolute that it becomes necessary to question what makes reality possible. We should emphasize that, on one hand, the rejection of Hegelian ontology does not lead Deleuze to some form of deontological thought. Although he denies any preconstituted structure of being or any ideological order of existence, Deleuze still operates on the highest planes of ontological speculation. Once again, to reject Hegelian ontology is not to reject ontology tout court. Deleuze insists instead on alternatives within the ontological tradition. On the other hand, however, we should be careful from the outset to distinguish this from a Heideggerian return to ontology, most importantly because Deleuze will only accept “superficial” responses to the question “What makes being possible?” In other words, he limits us to a strictly immanent and materialist ontological discourse that refuses any deep or hidden foundation of being. There is nothing veiled or negative about Deleuze's being; it is fully expressed in the world. Being, in this sense, is superficial, positive, and full. Deleuze refuses any “intellectualist” account of being, any account that in any way subordinates being to thought, that poses thinking as the supreme form of being. 3 There are numerous contributions to this project of a materialist ontology throughout the history of philosophy-such as Spinoza, Marx, Nietzsche, and Lucretius-and we will refer to them in our discussion to provide illustrative points of reference. We will focus, however, on Deleuze's constitutive conception of practice as a foundation of ontology. The radical negation of the nondialectical pars destruens emphasizes that no preconstituted order is available to define the organization of being. Practice provides the terms for a material pars construens; practice is what makes the constitution of being possible. The investigation of the nature of power allows Deleuze to bring substance to the materialist discourse and to raise the theory of practice to the level of ontology. The foundation of being, then, resides both on a corporeal and on a mental plane, in the complex dynamics of behavior, in the superficial interactions of bodies. This is not an Althusserian “theoretical practice, ” but rather a more practical conception of practice, autonomous of any “theoricist tendency, ” a “practical practice” that is oriented principally toward the ontological rather than the epistemological realm. The only nature available to ontological discourse is an absolutely artificial conception of nature, a hybrid nature, a nature produced in practice-further removed than a second nature, an nth nature. This approach to ontology is as new as the infinitely plastic universe of cyborgs and as old as the tradition of materialist philosophy. What will be important throughout our discussion is that the traditionally fundamental terms-such as necessity, reason, nature, and being-though shaken from their transcendental fixity, still serve as a foundation because they acquire a certain consistency and substance in our world. Being, now historicized and materialized, is delimited by the outer bounds of the contemporary imagination, of the contemporary field of practice.

I elaborate these conceptions of nondialectical negation and constitutive practice in Deleuze's work by reading the evolution of his thought, that is, by following the progression of critical questions that guide his investigations during successive periods. The evolution of Deleuze's thought unfolds as he directs his attention sequentially to a series of authors in the philosophical canon and poses them each a specific question. His work on Bergson offers a critique of negative ontology and proposes in its stead an absolutely positive movement of being that rests on an efficient and internal notion of causality. To the negative movement of determination, he opposes the positive movement of differentiation; to the dialectical unity of the One and the Multiple, he opposes the irreducible multiplicity of becoming. The question of the organization or the constitution of the world, however, of the being of becoming, pushes Deleuze to pose these ontological issues in ethical terms. Nietzsche allows him to transpose the results of ontological speculation to an ethical horizon, to the field of forces, of sense and value, where the positive movement of being becomes the affirmation of being. The thematic of power in Nietzsche provides the theoretical passage that links Bergsonian ontology to an ethics of active expression. Spinoza covers this same passage and extends it to practice. Just as Nietzsche poses the affirmation of speculation, Spinoza poses the affirmation of practice, or joy, at the center of ontology. Deleuze argues that Spinoza's is an ontological conception of practice; Spinoza conceives practice, that is, as constitutive of being. In the precritical world of Spinoza's practical philosophy, Deleuze's thought finally discovers a real autonomy from the Hegelian problematic.

One lesson to be learned from this philosophical project is to highlight the nuances that define an antagonism. Once we stop clouding the issue with crude oppositions and recognize instead the specificity of an antagonism, we can begin to bring out finer nuances in our terminology. For example, when I pose the question of the foundations of poststructuralist thought I mean to contest the claim that this thought is properly characterized as antifoundationalism. To pose the issue as an exclusive opposition is, in effect, to credit the enemy with too much force, with too much theoretical terrain. Poststructuralism does critique a certain notion of foundation, but only to affirm another notion that is more adequate to its ends. Against a transcendental foundation we find an immanent one; against a given, teleological foundation we find a material, open one. 4 A similar nuance must be made in our discussion of causality. When we look closely at Deleuze's critique of causality we find not only a powerful rejection of the final cause and the formal cause, but also an equally powerful affirmation of the efficient cause as central to his philosophical project. Deleuze's ontology draws on the tradition of causal arguments and develops notions of both being's “productivity” and its “producibility, ” that is, of its aptitudes to produce and to be produced. I will argue that efficient causality, in fact, provides a key to a coherent account of Deleuze's entire discourse on difference. The nuances in the use of “foundation” and “causality” are perhaps best summarized by the distinction between order and organization. By the order of being, of truth, or of society I intend the structure imposed as necessary and eternal from above, from outside the material scene of forces; I use organization, on the other hand, to designate the coordination and accumulation of accidental (in the philosophical sense, i.e., nonnecessary) encounters and developments from below, from within the immanent field of forces. In other words, I do not conceive of organization as a blueprint of development or as the projected vision of an avant-garde, but rather as an immanent creation or composition of a relationship of consistency and coordination. In this sense, organization, the composition of creative forces, is always an art.

Throughout this study we will encounter unresolved problems and propositions that are powerfully suggestive but perhaps not clearly and rigorously delimited. We do not look to Deleuze here, however, simply to find the solutions to contemporary theoretical problems. More important, we inquire into his thought in order to investigate the proposals of a new problematic for research after the poststructuralist rupture, to test our footing on a terrain where new grounds of philosophical and political thought are possible. What we ask of Deleuze, above all, is to teach us the contemporary possibilities of philosophy.

Read more...

Kirk Ludwig , Donald Davidson (Contemporary Philosophy in Focus)

Kirk Ludwig , Donald Davidson (Contemporary Philosophy in Focus)
Cambridge University Press | ISBN 0521793823 | 2003 | PDF | 1.2 MB | 256 pages

Written by a distinguished roster of philosophers, this volume includes chapters on truth and meaning; the philosophy of action; radical interpretation; philosophical psychology; knowledge of the external world; other minds and our own minds; and the implications of Davidson’s work for literary theory. Donald Davidson has been one of the most influential figures in modern analytic philosophy and has made significant contributions to a wide range of subjects. Embodied in a series of landmark essays stretching over nearly 40 years, his principal work exhibits a unity rare among philosophers contributing on so many diverse fronts. Kirk Ludwig, the recipient of two grants from the National Endowment for the Humanities, has taught at the University of Florida’s Department of Philosophy since 1995. His areas of research specialization include philosophy of language, epistemology, and philosophy of mind. He has contributed chapters to a number of volumes on these topics as well as published articles in Philosophical Quarterly, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Mind and Language, and elsewhere.

link

Read more...

Michael L. Morgan & Peter Eli Gordon - The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy

The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy


Michael L. Morgan & Peter Eli Gordon, "The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy" (Cambridge Companions to Religion)
Cambridge University Press (2007) | English | ISBN 0521813123 | 390 pages | PDF | 2.06 MB


The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy is a collection of original essays that examine the work of some of the most important Jewish thinkers of the modern era – the period extending from the seventeenth century to the late twentieth century. Editors Michael L. Morgan and Peter Eli Gordon have brought together a group of world-renowned scholars to paint a broad and rich picture of the tradition of modern Jewish philosophy over a period of four hundred years. Beginning with the seventeenth century, modern Jewish philosophy developed among thinkers who responded to the new science and modern philosophy in the course of reflecting on the nature of Judaism and Jewish life. The essays address themes that are central to the tradition of modern Jewish philosophy – language and revelation, autonomy and authority, the problem of evil, Messianism, the influence of Kant, and feminism – and discuss in depth the work of major thinkers such as Spinoza, Mendelssohn, Cohen, Buber, Rosenzweig, Fackenheim, Soloveitchik, Strauss, Levinas, Maimon, Benjamin, Derrida, Scholem, and Arendt.

link

Read more...

Ebook directory on Philosophy (eserver.org)

link

The heart of Philosophy is our collection of canonical texts. Every year more texts go out of copywrite faster than we can identify and collect them. Any help finding and collecting these texts (in the origional languages and in translation) would be greatly appreciated.
various texts in .txt format

Read more...

Thomas Holden - The Architecture of Matter: Galileo to Kant

link on Maquinas de Mundo





















The Architecture of Matter: Galileo to Kant

Oxford University Press, USA
ISBN 0199263264
2004 Edition
PDF 191 Pages 830 KB


Thomas Holden presents a fascinating study of theories of matter in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. These theories were plagued by a complex of interrelated problems concerning matter's divisibility, composition, and internal architecture. Is any material body infinitely divisible? Must we posit atoms or elemental minima from which bodies are ultimately composed? Are the parts of material bodies themselves material concreta? Or are they merely potentialities or possible existents? Questions such as these - and the press of subtler questions hidden in their amibiguities - deeply unsettled philosophers of the early modern period. They seemed to expose serious paradoxes in the new world view pioneered by Galileo, Descartes, and Newton. The new science's account of a fundamentally geometrical Creation, mathematicizable and intelligible to the human inquirer, seemed to be under threat. This was a great scandal, and the philosophers of the period accordingly made various attempts to disarm the paradoxes. All the great figures address the issue: most famously Leibniz and Kant, but also Galileo, Hobbes, Newton, Hume, and Reid, in addition to a crowd of lesser figures. Thomas Holden offers a brilliant synthesis of these discussions and presents his own overarching interpretation of the controversy, locating the underlying problem in the tension between the early moderns' account of material parts on the one hand and the programme of the geometrization of nature on the other.

Read more...

The Coherence of Kant's Transcendental Idealism

link on Máquinas de Mundo


The Coherence of Kant's Transcendental Idealism
Publisher: Springer(2004-05-11)
ISBN-10: 1402025807
PDF 2.3 Mb 295 pages


This book presents a new interpretation of Kant’s theory of knowledge that emphasizes the coherence and plausibility of his doctrine of transcendental idealism. Many interpreters believe that Kant’s transcendental idealism is an incoherent theory. Some have attempted to respond to this charge. Yet, as the author demonstrates, the interpretations that seek to vindicate Kant’s theory continue to be committed to some claims that evoke the charge of incoherence. One type of claim which does so is connected to the contradictory notion of subjective necessity. The other type of claim is related to the supposition that knowledge of the reality of appearances entails knowledge of the reality of things in themselves. The interpretation presented in this book does not involve any of these claims. Part One of this book presents an analysis of Kant’s concept of a priori knowledge and of his response to skepticism about synthetic a priori knowledge that specifies the content of such knowledge without invoking the notion of subjective necessity. Part Two presents an account of the non-spatiotemporality of things in themselves that does not entail knowledge of the reality of things in themselves. Part Three presents a new interpretation of transcendental synthesis, the transcendental "I" and of the role of transcendental self-consciousness in synthetic a priori knowledge which emphasizes the originality of Kant’s account of self-knowledge and subjectivity. The arguments presented in this book relate Kant’s ideas to current debates in epistemology, metaphysics and the philosophy of mind in a way that underscores their invaluable relevance to present-day philosophical discourse.

Read more...

Foucault and Kant (some references)

link: ahp.yorku.ca

Some articles (in english) on Foucault and Kant

Read more...

Naamah Akavia - Writing “The Case of Ellen West”: Clinical Knowledge and Historical Representation

Akavia , Naamah. Writing “The Case of Ellen West”: Clinical Knowledge and Historical RepresentationScience in Context 21(1), 119–144 (2008). (PDF file)

Argument
“The Case of Ellen West” was published by the Swiss psychiatrist, Ludwig Binswanger, in 1944–1945. The case-history depicts the illness and suicide of a young woman who was his patient twenty years earlier. It came to be considered one of the paradigmatic studies of the newly established discipline of Daseinsanalyse, an attempt to synthesize existential philosophy and therapeutic practice. This paper analyzes the case-study, employing newly uncovered archival material to expose important details regarding the treatment of Ellen West (a pseudonym) and the posthumous writing of her case-history. The richness of the archival sources and the various historiographical characteristics they exhibit raise methodological questions about the potentialities and limitations of historical representation. The new data will thus serve as a platform from which to explore and discuss more generally the problems involved in historical reconstruction – of both subjective experience and clinical knowledge – and the questions of authorship and intertextuality in the genre of the case-history.

Read more...

Daniel Defoe - The History of the Devil (1727)

img261/4778/imagethepoliticalhistorzb7.jpg

a contemporary cover

link: archive.org (and here, 1840 edition)

Domain: Literature, Religion. Genre: Treatise, Satire, Novel. Country: England, Britain, Europe.

The Political History of the Devil – or, to give it its full title, The Political History of the Devil, as well Ancient as Modern: in Two Parts. Part I. Containing a State of the Devil’s Circumstances, and the various Turns of his Affairs, from his Expulsion out of Heaven, to the Creation of Man; with Remarks on the several Mistakes concerning the Reason and Manner of his Fall. Also his Proceedings with Mankind ever since Adam, to the first planting of the Christian Religion in the World. Part II. Containing his more private Conduct, down to the Present Times: his Government, his Appearances, his Manner of Working, and the Tools he works with. Bad as he is, the Devil may be abus’d, Be falsly charg’d, and causelessly accus’d, When Men, unwilling to be blam’d alone, Shift off those Crimes on Him which are their Own – is a work of some 258 octavo pages. It offers a serio-comic satire on both mankind and popular ideas of the devil. Whilst Defoe sees evidence of the devil’s handiwork everywhere, he mocks medieval and Catholic images of a terrifying devil “broiling [sinners] upon Gridirons, hanging them up upon Hooks”. Rather than seeing the devil as the unique source of human iniquity, Defoe has the devil return to earth after hundreds of years of absence to discover mankind committing evil acts without having consulted him, and then blaming him as the cause. Furthermore, the devil discovers that human beings are capable of far more devious and criminal acts than he could ever have conceived or devised. Thus, the work recognizes the Divine order of the world, and Defoe proves himself a devout Presbyterian; but the work attributes disorder, first, to the devil’s desire to wreak chaos upon earth and, secondly, to the manner in which man may, on the one hand, be persuaded by the devil to disrupt the initial order of Eden, but, on the other, act on his own with evil intent.

As the extended title indicates, The Political History of the Devil is divided into two parts. In the first part Defoe discusses Biblical narrative and devotes himself to the devil’s influence upon human beings. In the second part he focuses on modern politics and government, pointing out how recent and contemporary politicians have been influenced by the devil.

In the first part, comprising eleven chapters, Defoe claims that the devil has two undeniable traits: (1) he is a believer and (2) he fears God. Defoe believes that the devil could be an historian were he ever to tell the truth, but that is not his way. The devil has no permanent or visible shape. He is capable of entering any shape he desires to achieve his ends. With his multiple identities, he is identified by many names in the Hebrew Scriptures or in the New Testament: the Serpent (Gen. iii.1), the great red Dragon (Rev. xii.3), Satan (Job i.), the Prince of the power of the air (Eph.ii.2), and Lucifer (Isa.xiv.12), to l [source]

Read more...

List of Complete Works of Martin Heidegger

link

This is a list of the complete works of Martin Heidegger. The numbers are those assigned to each work in the official collection, the Gesamtausgabe, which is still an ongoing effort. The Gesamtausgabe is published by Vittorio Klostermann, Frankfurt am Main.

Read more...

Slavoj Zizek - Hegel - Chesterton: German Idealism and Christianity

link

According to a commonplace, Judaism (and Islam) is a "pure" monotheism, while Christianity, with its Trinity, is a compromise with polytheism; Hegel even designates Islam as THE "religion of sublimity" at its purest, as the universalization of the Jewish monotheism:

"In Mohammedanism the limited principle of the Jews is expanded into universality and thereby overcome. Here, God is no longer, as with the Asiatics, contemplated as existent in immediately sensuous mode but is apprehended as the one infinite sublime Power beyond all the multiplicity of the world. Mohammedanism is, therefore, in the strictest sense of the world, the religion of sublimity."1

This, perhaps, explains why there is so much anti-Semitism in Islam: because of the extreme proximity of the two religions. In Hegelese, in Judaism, Islam encounters ITSELF in its "oppositional determination," in the mode of particularity. Against this, one should argue that it is Judaism which is an "abstract negation" of polytheism and, as such, still haunted by it (Jehovah - plural; do not celebrate other gods IN FRONT OF ME; etc.), while Christianity is the only TRUE monotheism, since it includes self-differentiation into the One - its lesson is that, in order to have truly One, you need THREE. Here Hegel's logic of triads gets stuck into a deadlock: the triad that offers itself is that of Judaism - Christianity - Islam: first the immediate/abstract monotheism which, as the price to be paid for its immediate character, has to be embodied in a particular ethnic group (which is why Jews renounce all proselytism); then Christianity; then Islam, the only TRUE universal monotheism. What would be an alternative here?

Read more...

Pedro Costa Rego - Reflexão e fundamento: sobre a relação entre gosto e conhecimento na estética de Kant

REGO, Pedro Costa. Reflexão e fundamento: sobre a relação entre gosto e conhecimento na estética de Kant. Kriterion [online]. 2005, vol. 46, no. 112

RESUMO

A Crítica da Faculdade do Juízo, de Kant, é primordialmente uma investigação crítica acerca de uma certa classe de juízos chamados reflexionantes, que se subdivide em dois grupos, estéticos e teleológicos, e se define em oposição a uma outra classe, a dos chamados juízos determinantes. Nosso objetivo neste artigo é elaborar a hipótese de um privilégio fundacional do juízo reflexionante estético relativamente ao conhecimento determinante. Para tanto, pretendemos cumprir duas etapas. Em primeiro lugar, procederemos a uma análise da conexão entre os temas centrais — e aparentemente dissociados — do belo e da faculdade do juízo enquanto tal que justifica a passagem do projeto de uma crítica do gosto ao de uma crítica do juízo e delimita como alvo da obra o fundamento de determinação (Bestimmungsgrund) de uma "intersubjetividade" conceitualmente indeterminada. Em segundo lugar, passaremos à análise da relação entre a reflexão e o princípio da finalidade da natureza, com base na Introdução da terceira Crítica, a fim de identificar, na formulação "prática" do princípio do gosto, o germe de uma anterioridade que subordina a determinação à reflexão estética.

Palavras-Chave: Reflexão, Finalidade, Juízo de Gosto, Faculdade do Juízo


ABSTRACT

Kant's Critique of Judgment is chiefly a critical investigation into a certain class of judgments identified as "reflective", divided into the aesthetic and the teleological sub-classes and defined in opposition to those termed by Kant "determinant judgments". In this paper I intend to elaborate, in two expositive moments, the hypothesis of a foundational primacy of reflective aesthetic judgment over determinant knowledge. Firstly, I analyse the connection between the main themes — apparently dissociated — of beautiful and faculty of judgment in order to disclose both the ground of Kant's move from a Critique of Taste into a Critique of Judgment and the determining ground of a conceptually indeterminate intersubjectivity considered as the main aim of the work. In the next step I investigate the relationship between reflection and the principle of finality of nature on the basis of third Critique's Introduction in order to verify, through the "practical formula" of the principle of taste, the accuracy of the thesis supporting the primacy of aesthetic reflection over determination.

Keywords: Reflection, Finality, Judgment of Taste, Faculty of Judgment


Read more...

Fernando Vidal - La psychologie empirique et son historicisation pendant l’Aufklärung

link


Pendant le XVIIIème siècle en Allemagne, la psychologie empirique atteint un degré d’autonomie considérable. Dans le système des connaissances, la science naturelle de l’âme unie au corps se détache de la pneumatologie pour devenir une discipline de base de l’anthropologie, ou « science de l’homme ». Quant à sa présence dans la culture bourgeoise et dans les institutions académiques, la psychologie empirique s’élabore dans des genres « populaires » (essais, romans, revues) et en même temps s’intègre à l’université, sous la forme d’enseignements, de traités et de manuels. C’est d’une façon tout à fait originale et inconnue dans les autres disciplines scientifiques qui prennent corps à l’époque, que l’histoire de la psychologie, comme espèce historiographique, contribue à délimiter la nouvelle discipline et à renforcer son autonomie naissante. C’est ce que nous étudierons ici en suivant le chemin qui relie les fragments épars d’histoire de la psychologie que l’on trouve dans l’Histoire critique de la philosophie de Johann Jacob Brucker (1742-1747) et l’Histoire de la psychologie de Friedrich August Carus. Parue en 1808 à titre posthume, celle-ci constitue la première publication en son genre.

Mots-clés : psychologie empirique, anthropologie, science de l’homme, historiographie, pneumatologie, association des idées, Brucker, Carus, Hißmann, Wolff.

Empirical psychology attained a considerable degree of autonomy during the XVIIIth century in Germany. Within the system of knowledge, psychology, as natural science of the soul joined with the body, detached itself from pneumatology, and became a basic discipline of anthropology, or general « science of man ». It also entered bourgeois culture and learned institutions. On the one hand, it adopted « popular » forms (essays, novels, magazines). On the other hand, it became the subject of academic teaching, textbooks, and treatises. The development of the history of psychology as a historiographical genre helped define the new discipline, and reinforced its nascent autonomy. This article will study such development as it took place between the scattered fragments of a history of psychology included in Johann Jacob Brucker’s Critical history of philosophy (1742-1747) and the posthumous publication in 1808 of Friedrich August Carus’s History of psychology, the first of its kind.

Keywords : empirical psychology, anthropology, science of Man, historiography, pneumatology, Association of Ideas, Brucker, Carus, Hißmann, Wolff.

Read more...

The Complete Works of Chuang Tzu - translated by Burton Watson

link1, link2

http://www.takaoclub.com/foxmyths/WuCheng/ChuangTzu1.jpg

Contents

1 : Free and Easy Wandering
2 : Discussion on Making All Things Equal
3 : The Secret of Caring for Life
4 : In the World of Men
5 : The Sign of Virtue Complete
6 : The Great and Venerable Teacher
7 : Fit for Emperors and Kings
8 : Webbed Toes

9 : Horses' Hoofs
10 : Riffling Trunks
11 : Let It Be, Leave It Alone
12 : Heaven and Earth
13 : The Way of Heaven
14 : The Turning of Heaven
15 : Constrained in Will
16 : Mending the Inborn Nature
17 : Autumn Floods

18 : Perfect Happiness
19 : Mastering Life
20 : The Mountain Tree
21 : T'ien Tzu-fang
22 : Knowledge Wandered North
23 : Keng-sang C'hu
24 : Hsu Wu-kei
25 : Tse-yang

26 : External Things
27 : Inputed Words
28 : Giving Away a Throne
29 : Robber Chih
30 : Discoursing on Swords
31 : The Old Fishermman
32 : Lieh Yu-k'ou
33 : The World


Read more...

Tim Lewens - The philosophy of biology: a selection of readings and resources

link: hps.cam.ac.uk

The literature on the philosophy of biology is enormous; what follows only scratches the surface. Here I have restricted myself mainly to evolutionary biology, although there are short sections on evolutionary epistemology and evolutionary ethics. I have tried to include a handful of the best, the most interesting or the most often slated books and articles under each topic heading. These selections are intended as starting points for the interested student. Those who want to go further will have to follow their noses. Sterelny and Griffiths (1999) provide useful assistance to nose followers in the form of very up-to-date reading lists at the end of each of their chapters. Their book would also be a good starting point for researchers interested in topics that are not covered here – for example, issues in the philosophy of molecular biology and the philosophy of ecology, or traditional questions for philosophy of biology such as how to define life and how to define fitness.


Read more...

Hegel E-Books

http://www.hegelbrasil.org/hegel.jpg

Primary and secondary texts. Various editions and languages

and

Read more...

Blog Archive

Lorem Ipsum

"All testing, all confirmation and disconfirmation of a hypothesis takes place already within a system. And this system is not a more or less arbitrary and doubtful point of departure for all our arguments; no it belongs to the essence of what we call an argument. The system is not so much the point of departure, as the element in which our arguments have their life."
- Wittgenstein

Lorem Ipsum

"Le poète ne retient pas ce qu’il découvre ; l’ayant transcrit, le perd bientôt. En cela réside sa nouveauté, son infini et son péril"

René Char, La Bibliothèque est en feu (1956)


  © Blogger template Shush by Ourblogtemplates.com 2009

Back to TOP